Conjecture Et Refutation In An Argumentative Essay

Popper -- Science versus non-science: Conjecture and refutation.

 

Popper is one of the philosophers of science who has had the biggest impact on the practice of science.

 

In this paper Popper is asking two related questions:

1)      How do we determine whether or not a theory is scientific? (This does not refer to importance or truth or meaningfulness or acceptability.)

2)      What is the scientific method?

 


Pre Popper; Inductive Scientific Method

 

Step One: Make Observations

These observations are the premises in an inductive argument the conclusion of which is:

Step Two: Make Theory/Hypothesis

Step Three: Test Theory

            You do this by making more observations.

 

Example:

 

Here is a black crow.

The crows around Catt Hall are black.

The crows around the Union are black.

The crows around the gates of hell are black.

All crows are black.                                          ß This is my theory.

 

How do I test the theory? I go to the Bahamas and see if the crows are black there.

 

Problems with this method:

1)      Psychological.  It is very easy to find evidence to confirm something that you already believe and very easy to ignore evidence that conflicts with something that you already believe.

2)      Methodological. You can’t collect observations unless you already have a theory about what you are trying to observe.  Popper would argue that this crowologist had to have a theory about crows being black before she could collect the first premise.

3)      Logical.  Remember that this is an inductive argument and don’t present the conclusion as certain. 

 

Popper’s solution:  Falsificationism.

 

Scientists ought not to be trying to find evidence that confirms their theories, rather they should be trying to find evidence that conflicts with their theories.

 

A theory is falsifiable if you can imagine an observation that you could make that would cause you to reject the theory.

 

Example

 

If all crows are black then the crows in Cancun should be black.

The crows in Cancun are red.

It is not the case that all crows are black.

 

The logical structure of this argument:

If H then O

Not O    

Not H

 

If the hypothesis is true than I predict observation O.

I did not/could not observe O.

Therefore the hypothesis is not true.

 

Note that this is a valid deductive argument.

 

 

1)      For something to count as scientific Popper thinks that we need to be able to imagine an observation that could be made that would cause us to reject the hypothesis.

a.       In order to test a hypothesis we need to try to falsify it.

b.      The less likely the observation, or in other words the riskier the prediction, the better the test of a theory.

2)      The question that we need to ask now is: “Where do hypotheses come from?” and Popper’s answer is that scientists make them up (conjecture).

a.       Popper thinks that since there is no recipe for coming up with hypotheses (they are a result of the individual creative genius of scientists) that we don’t actually start doing science until we start thinking about falsifying out hypotheses.

 

Be sure that you can explain how Popper’s falsificationism meets all three of the problems that he raises for an inductive scientific method.

 

A real example!!

Popper thinks that his falsificationism is what distinguishes science from non science, and he uses the examples of the marxist theory of history, psychoanalysis, and Einstein and the Eddington experiment to show this.

 

He thought that Einstein’s theory of gravity was the only one that was really science because it was the only one that was falsifiable.  Here is how the example goes:

 

Einstein

  • According to Newton, light traveled in straight lines.  Einstein’s theory of relativity predicted that light would be affected by gravity.  That when light traveled past a massive object, it would bend.
  • Einstein’s theory was not consistent with any possible observation.  If we observed that light did not bend when it passed a massive object, we would think that E’s theory was false. 
  • Unfortunately, it is very difficult to see whether or not light bends.

 

Eddington thought up a great experiment that would allow us to make this very observation.

 

  • He noted that if E. was correct, the sun would be massive enough to bend the light arriving from distant stars.  All that we needed to do was to compare our observations of the stars at night (when the light doesn’t go past our sun) with the position of the stars during the day (when their light does go past our sun).  The only trouble is that we can’t observe the starts during the day. 
  • Eddington’s genius was to observe the stars during the day when there was a complete eclipse of the sun.
  • Eddington made a prediction. If Einstein was wrong, then the position of the stars would be the same at night and during the eclipse. The theory is incompatible with certain possible observations.
  • This is risky: If the predicted effect was absent, then the theory would be refuted.
  • Click here for a diagram of how this works.

 

With the other theories, it is impossible to describe a behavior that is not consistent with them.  It is impossible to make a risky prediction.

 

Popper thinks that the way to test whether or not a theory is scientific is to ask yourself, “what would it take to make this theory false?”  If the answer is nothing, it isn’t science.

 

 

“The criterion of the scientific status of a theory is its falsifiability, or refutability, or testability.”

 

The other three theories are untestable, but for different reasons:

  • Astrology doesn’t pass this test. It escapes being falsified by being vague.  Vague predictions are irrefutable.  Ex. “You will learn something today.” Can you imagine a day in which you learn absolutely nothing?  No.
  • The Marxist theory of history made predictions and was falsified.  But, the holders of this theory reinterpreted their theory and evidence, in other words, they made ad hoc changes to the theory.  If I change my theory every time I get falsifying evidence, then it becomes impossible to refute.
  • Psychoanalytic theories are straightforwardly not testable, or irrefutable.  I cannot imagine a case in which they could be untrue.  This is not to say that it isn’t useful or that it fails to describe some parts of the world accurately.  But, it is not science.

 

This is the problem of demarcation. Drawing a line between science and other ways of knowing.  The criterion of falsification is the solution to this problem.

 

'); doc.close(); function init(b, config) { b.addVar({ 'abTests[0][testName]': 'cssJsInjectionInlineLinkColor', 'abTests[0][bucketValue]': 3, 'abTests[1][testName]': 'indexUniversalWrapper', 'abTests[1][bucketValue]': 0, 'abTests[2][testName]': 'videoRangeToPlay', 'abTests[2][bucketValue]': 1, 'abTests[3][testName]': 'videoControls', 'abTests[3][bucketValue]': 1, 'abTests[4][testName]': 'cssJsInjection', 'abTests[4][bucketValue]': 0, 'ptax': 'tho_english-grammar', 'tax0': 'tho', 'tax1': 'tho_humanities', 'tax2': 'tho_languages', 'tax3': 'tho_english-grammar', 'tax4': 'tho_grammar-glossary', 'templateId': '65', 'templateName': 'flexTemplate', 'templateView': 'PERSONAL_COMPUTER', 'tmog': 'g16212cec4e069702d31302d31342d392d39352d311bcba', 'mint': 'g16212cec4e069702d31302d31342d392d39352d311bcba', 'idstamp': 'g16212cec4e069702d31302d31342d392d39352d311bcba', 'dataCenter': 'us-east-1', 'serverName': 'ip-10-14-9-95-1', 'serverVersion': '2.40.7', 'resourceVersion': '2.40.7', 'cc': 'UA', 'city': '', 'lat': '50.45', 'lon': '30.523', 'rg': '', 'clientTimestamp': new Date().getTime(), 'globeTimestamp': 1520733963488, 'referrer': document.referrer, 'sessionPc': '1', 'userAgent[familyName]': 'IE', 'userAgent[versionMajor]': '11', 'userAgent[versionMinor]': '0', 'userAgent[osName]': 'Windows 7', 'userAgent[osVersion]': '6.1', 'userAgent[mobile]': 'false', 'userAgent[raw]': 'Mozilla/5.0 (Windows NT 6.1; WOW64; Trident/7.0; rv:11.0) like Gecko' }); b.init({ beacon_url: 'https://rd.about.com/boomerang/reference', user_ip: '178.159.37.71', site_domain: 'thoughtco.com', BW: { enable: false }, DFPTiming: {} }); } if (document.addEventListener) { document.addEventListener("onBoomerangLoaded", function(e) { // e.detail.BOOMR is a reference to the BOOMR global object init(e.detail.BOOMR); }); } else if (document.attachEvent) { // IE 6, 7, 8 we use onPropertyChange and look for propertyName === "onBoomerangLoaded" document.attachEvent("onpropertychange", function(e) { if (!e) e=event; if (e.propertyName === "onBoomerangLoaded") { // e.detail.BOOMR is a reference to the BOOMR global object init(e.detail.BOOMR); } }); } })();(function() { var article = document.getElementById('article_1-0'); if (article && !article.gtmPageView) { article.gtmPageView = {"description":"Refutation is the part of an argument in which a speaker or writer counters opposing points of view. Here are some examples and observations from other writers.","errorType":"","updateDate":"2017-04-22","authorId":"22176","contentGroup":"Articles","documentId":1692036,"lastEditingAuthorId":"22176","lastEditingUserId":"148122552371372","characterCount":5855,"templateId":"65","socialTitle":"What Part of an Argument Is the Refutation?","title":"Refutation Definition and Examples" || document.title || '',"currentPageOrdinal":"","previousPageOrdinal":"","entryType":"direct","pageviewType":"standard","templateVariation":"","publishDate":"2007-03-05","numOfImages":1,"numOfPages":1,"numOfArticleWords":"","numOfInlineLinks":"","excludeFromComscore":false,"socialImage":"https://fthmb.tqn.com/MuW_EsM3-9d_-SuUmB-ydEs1i0g=/735x0/blackboard_confirmation-56af8f1c5f9b58b7d01a8d21.jpg","numOfMapLabels":"","isErrorPage":false,"instartLogicDelivered":0,"internalSessionId":"g16212cec4e069702d31302d31342d392d39352d311bcba","internalRequestId":"g16212cec4e069702d31302d31342d392d39352d311bcba","taxonomyNodes":[[{"documentId":4122478,"shortName":"ThoughtCo"},{"documentId":4133358,"shortName":"Humanities"},{"documentId":4133094,"shortName":"Languages"},{"documentId":4133049,"shortName":"English Grammar"},{"documentId":4133037,"shortName":"Glossary of Key Terms"}]],"isCommerceDocument":false,"experienceTypeName":"","fullUrl":"https://www.thoughtco.com/refutation-argument-1692036" + location.hash,"experienceType":"single page"}; } }()); (function() { Mntl.utilities.readyAndDeferred(function($container){ var $masonryInstance = $('#masonry-list1_1-0'); if ($masonryInstance.data('no-js')) return; Mntl.MasonryList.init($container, $masonryInstance, {stretch: '.card__img, .card--no-image .card__content'}); }); })();(function() { Mntl.utilities.readyAndDeferred(function($container){ var $masonryInstance = $('#masonry-list2_1-0'); if ($masonryInstance.data('no-js')) return; Mntl.MasonryList.init($container, $masonryInstance, {stretch: '.card__img, .card--no-image .card__content'}); }); })();

0 Thoughts to “Conjecture Et Refutation In An Argumentative Essay

Leave a comment

L'indirizzo email non verrà pubblicato. I campi obbligatori sono contrassegnati *